Illusions - novelonlinefull.com
You’re read light novel Illusions Part 19 online at NovelOnlineFull.com. Please use the follow button to get notification about the latest chapter next time when you visit NovelOnlineFull.com. Use F11 button to read novel in full-screen(PC only). Drop by anytime you want to read free – fast – latest novel. It’s great if you could leave a comment, share your opinion about the new chapters, new novel with others on the internet. We’ll do our best to bring you the finest, latest novel everyday. Enjoy
FOOTNOTES:
[1] A history of the distinction is given by Brierre de Boismont, in his work _On Illusions_ (translated by R. T. Hulme, 1859). He says that Arnold (1806) first defined hallucination, and distinguished it from illusion. Esquirol, in his work, _Des Maladies Mentales_ (1838), may be said to have fixed the distinction. (See Hunt's translation, 1845, p.
111.)
[2] This fact has been fully recognized by writers on the pathology of the subject; for example, Griesinger, _Mental Pathology and Therapeutics_ (London, 1867), p. 84; Baillarger, article, "Des Hallucinations," in the _Memoires de l'Academie Royale de Medecine_, tom. xii. p. 273, etc; Wundt, _Physiologische Psychologie_, p. 653.
[3] I here touch on the distinction between the psychological and the philosophical view of perception, to be brought out more fully by-and-by.
[4] It might even be urged that the order here adopted is scientifically the best, since sense-perception is the earliest form of knowledge, introspected facts being known only in relation to perceived facts. But if the mind's knowledge of its own states is thus later in time, it is earlier in the logical order, that is to say, it is the most strictly presentative form of knowledge.
[5] Here and elsewhere I use the word "impression" for the whole complex of sensation which is present at the moment. It may, perhaps, not be unnecessary to add that, in employing this term, I am making no a.s.sumption about the independent existence of external objects.
[6] Psychological usage has now pretty well subst.i.tuted the term "image"
for "idea," in order to indicate an individual (as distinguished from a general) representation of a sensation or percept. It might, perhaps, be desirable to go further in this process of differentiating language, and to distinguish between a sensational image, _e.g._ the representation of a colour, and a perceptional image, as the representation of a coloured object. It may be well to add that, in speaking of a fusion of an image and a sensation, I do not mean that the former exists apart for a single instant. The term "fusion" is used figuratively to describe the union of the two sides or aspects of a complete percept.
[7] This impulse to fill in visual elements not actually present is strikingly ill.u.s.trated in people's difficulty in recognizing the gap in the field of vision answering to the insensitive "blind" spot on the retina. (See Helmholtz, _Physiologische Optik_, p. 573, _et seq._)
[8] This relation will be more fully discussed under the head of "Memory."
[9] I adopt this distinction from Dr. J. Hughlings Jackson. See his articles, "On Affections of Speech from Diseases of the Brain," in _Brain_, Nos. iii. and vii. The second stage might conveniently be named apperception, but for the special philosophical a.s.sociations of the term: _Problems of Life and Mind_, third series, p. 107. This writer employs the word "preperception" to denote this effect of previous perception.
[10] Such verbal suggestion, moreover, acting through a sense-impression, has something of that vividness of effect which belongs to all excitation of mental images by external stimuli.
[11] See Wundt, _Physiologische Psychologie_, p. 723.
[12] For a confirmation of the view adopted in the text, see Professor Bain, _The Senses and the Intellect_, Part II. ch. i. sec. 8; Herbert Spencer, _Principles of Psychology_, vol. i. p. 234, _et pa.s.sim_; Dr.
Ferrier, _The Functions of the Brain_, p. 258, _et seq._; Professor Wundt, _op. cit._, pp. 644, 645; G. H. Lowes, _Problems of Life and Mind_, vol. v. p. 445, _et seq._ For an opposite view, see Dr.
Carpenter, _Mental Physiology_, fourth edit., p. 220, etc.; Dr.
Maudsley, _The Physiology of Mind_, ch. v. p. 259, etc.
[13] See note, p. 22.
[14] Touch gives much by way of interpretation only when an individual object, for example a man's hat, is recognized by aid of this sense alone, in which case the perception distinctly involves the reproduction of a complete visual percept. I may add that the organ of smell comes next to that of hearing, with respect both to the range and definiteness of its simultaneous sensations, and to the amount of information furnished by these. A rough sense of distance as well as of direction is clearly obtainable by means of this organ. There seems to me no reason why an animal endowed with fine olfactory sensibility, and capable of an a.n.a.lytic separation of sense elements, should not gain a rough perception of an external order much more complete than our auditory perception, which is necessarily so fragmentary. This supposition appears, indeed, to be the necessary complement to the idea first broached, so far as I am aware, by Professor Croom Robertson, that to such animals, visual perception consists in a reference to a system of muscular feelings defined and bounded by strong olfactory sensations, rather than by tactual sensations as in our case.
[15] It may be said, perhaps, that the exceptional direction of attention, by giving an unusual intensity to the impression, causes us to exaggerate it just as in the case of a novel sensation. An effort of attention directed to any of our vague bodily sensations easily leads us to magnify its cause. A similar confusion may arise even in direct vision, when the objects are looked at in a dim light, through a want of proper accommodation. (See Sir D. Brewster, _op. cit._, letter i)
[16] They might also be distinguished as objective and subjective illusions, or as illusions _a posteriori_ and illusions _a priori_.
[17] _Die Schein-Bewegungen_, von Professor Dr. J.I. Hoppe (1879); _cf._ an ingenious article on "Optical Illusions of Motion," by Professor Silva.n.u.s P. Thompson, in _Brain_, October, 1880. These illusions frequently involve the co-operation of some preconception or expectation. For example, the apparent movement of a train when we are watching it and expecting it to move, involves both an element of sense-impression and of imagination. It is possible that the illusion of table-turning rests on the same basis, the table-turner being unaware of the fact of exerting a certain amount of muscular force, and vividly expecting a movement of the object.
[18] _Physiologische Optik_, p. 316.
[19] It is plain that this supposed error could only be brought under our definition of illusion by extending the latter, so as to include sense-perceptions which are contradicted by reason employing idealized elements of sense-impression, which, as Lewes has shown (_Problems of Life and Mind_, i. p. 260), make up the "extra-sensible world" of science.
[20] An ingenious writer, M. Binet, has tried to prove that the fusion of h.o.m.ogeneous sensations, having little difference of local colour, is an ill.u.s.tration of this principle. (See the _Revue Philosophique_, September, 1880.)
[21] Even the fusion of elementary sensations of colour, on the hypothesis of Young and Helmholtz, in a seemingly simple sensation may be explained to some extent by these circ.u.mstances, more especially the ident.i.ty of local interpretation.
[22] The perception of l.u.s.tre as a single quality seems to ill.u.s.trate a like error. There is good reason to suppose that this impression arises through, a difference of brightness in the two retinal images due to the regularly reflected light. And so when this inequality of retinal impression is imitated, as it may easily be by combining a black and a white surface in a stereoscope, we imagine that we are looking at one l.u.s.trous surface. (See Helmholtz, _Physiologische Optik_, p. 782, etc., and _Populare wissenschaftliche Vortrage_, 2tes Heft, p. 80.)
[23] The conditions of the production of these double images have been accurately determined by Helmholtz, who shows that the coalescence of impressions takes place whenever the object is so situated in the field of vision as to make it practically necessary that it should be recognized as one.
[24] These illusions are, of course, due in part to inattention, since close critical scrutiny is often sufficient to dispel them. They are also largely promoted by a preconception that the event is going to happen in a particular way. But of this more further on. I may add that the late Professor Clifford has argued ingeniously against the idea of the world being a continuum, by extending this idea of the wheel of life. (See _Lectures and Essays_, i. p. 112, _et seq._)
[25] It is supposed that in the case of every sense-organ there is always some minimum forces of stimulus at work, the effect of which on our consciousness is _nil_.
[26] See Helmholtz, _Physiologische Optik_, p. 603. Helmholtz's explanation is criticised by Dr. Hoppe, in the work already referred to (sec. vii), though I cannot see that his own theory of these movements is essentially different. The apparent movement of objects in vertigo, or giddiness, is probably due to the loss, through a physical cause, of the impressions made by the pressure of the fluid contents of the ear on the auditory fibres, by which the sense of equilibrium and of rotation is usually received. (See Ferrier, _Functions of the Brain_, pp. 60, 61.)
[27] I do not need here to go into the question whether, as Johannes Muller a.s.sumed, this is an original attribute of nerve-structure, or whether, as Wundt suggests, it is due simply to the fact that certain kinds of nervous fibre have, in the course of evolution, been slowly adapted to one kind of stimulus.
[28] I here refer to what is commonly supposed to be the vague innate difference of sensation according to the local origin, before this is rendered precise, and added to by experience and a.s.sociation.
[29] The illusory character of this simple mode of perception is seen best, perhaps, in the curious habit into which we fall of referring a sensation of contact or discomfort to the edge of the teeth, the hair, and the other insentient structures, and even to anything customarily attached to the sentient surface, as dress, a pen, graving tool, etc. On these curious illusions, see Lotze, _Mikrokosmus_, third edit., vol. ii.
p. 202, etc.; Taine, _De l'Intelligence_, tom. ii. p. 83, _et seq._
[30] Quoted by G.H. Lewes, _Problems of Life and Mind_, third series, p.
335. These illusions are supposed to involve an excitation of the nerve-fibres (whether sensory or motor) which run to the muscles and yield the so-called muscular sensations.
[31] It is brought out by Griesinger (_loc. cit._) and the other writers on the pathology of illusion already quoted, that in the case of subjective sensations of touch, taste, and smell, no sharp line can be drawn between illusion and hallucination.
[32] For a fuller account of these pathological disturbances of sensibility, see Griesinger; also Dr. A. Mayer, _Die Sinnestauschungen_.
[33] Helmholtz, _op. cit._, p. 600, _et seq._ These facts seem to point to the conclusion that at least some of the feelings by which we know that we are expending muscular energy are connected with the initial stage of the outgoing nervous process in the motor centres. In other pathological conditions the sense of weight by the muscles of the arms is similarly confused.
[34] Wundt (_Physiologische Psychologie_, p. 653) would exclude from illusions all those errors of sense-perception which have their foundation in the normal structure and function of the organs of sense.
Thus, he would exclude the effects of colour-contrast, _e.g._ the apparent modification of two colours in, juxtaposition towards their common boundary, which probably arises (according to E. Hering) from some mutual influence of the temporary state of activity of adjacent retinal elements. To me, however, these appear to be illusions, since they may be brought under the head of wrong _interpretations_ of sense-impressions. When we see a grey patch as rose-red, as though it were so independently of the action of the complementary light previously or simultaneously, that is to say, as though it would appear rose-red to an eye independently of this action, we surely misinterpret.
[35] Quoted by G.H. Lewes, _loc. cit._, p. 257.
[36] The subject of the perception of movement is too intricate to be dealt with fully here. I have only touched on it so far as necessary to ill.u.s.trate our general principle. For a fuller treatment of the subject, see the work of Dr. Hoppe, already referred to.
[37] The perception of magnitude is closely connected with that of distance, and is similarly apt to take an illusory form. I need only refer to the well-known simple optical contrivances for increasing the apparent magnitude of objects. I ought, perhaps, to add that I do not profess to give a complete account of optical illusions here, but only to select a few prominent varieties, with a view to ill.u.s.trate general principles of illusion. For a fuller account of the various mechanical arrangements for producing optical illusion, I must refer the reader to the writings of Sir D. Brewster and Helmholtz.
[38] Painters are well aware that the colours at the red end of the spectrum are apt to appear as advancing, while those of the violet end are known as retiring. The appearance of relief given by a gilded pattern on a dark blue as ground, is in part referable to the principle just referred to. In addition, it appears to involve a difference in the action of the muscles of accommodation in the successive adaptations of the eye to the most refrangible and the least refrangible rays. (See Brucke, _Die Physiologie der Farben_, sec. 17.)
[39] Helmholtz tells us (_Populare wissenschaftliche Vortrage_, 3tes Heft, p. 64) that even in a stereoscopic arrangement the presence of a wrong cast shadow sufficed to disturb the illusion.
[40] Among the means of giving a vivid sense of depth to a picture, emphasized by Helmholtz, is diminishing magnitude. It is obvious that the perceptions of real magnitude and distance are mutually involved.
When, for example, a picture represents a receding series of objects, as animals, trees, or buildings, the sense of the third dimension, is rendered much more clear.
[41] A striking example of this was given in a painting, by Andsell, of a sportsman in the act of shooting, exhibited in the Royal Academy in 1879.
[42] This is at least true of all near objects.
[43] Helmholtz remarks _(op. cit._, p. 628) that the difficulty of seeing the convex cast as concave is probably due to the presence of the cast shadow. This has, no doubt, some effect: yet the consideration urged in the text appears to me to be the most important one.
[44] _Populare wissenschaftliche Vortrage_, 3tes Heft, pp. 71, 72.