Home

Deductive Logic Part 12

Deductive Logic - novelonlinefull.com

You’re read light novel Deductive Logic Part 12 online at NovelOnlineFull.com. Please use the follow button to get notification about the latest chapter next time when you visit NovelOnlineFull.com. Use F11 button to read novel in full-screen(PC only). Drop by anytime you want to read free – fast – latest novel. It’s great if you could leave a comment, share your opinion about the new chapters, new novel with others on the internet. We’ll do our best to bring you the finest, latest novel everyday. Enjoy

An Inseparable Accident is one which belongs to all the members of a cla.s.s.

Blackness is a separable accident of man, an inseparable accident of coals.

-- 320. The attributes which belong to anything may be distinguished broadly under the two heads of essential and non-essential, or accidental. By the essential attributes of anything are meant those which are contained in, or which flow from, the definition. Now it may be questioned whether there can, in the nature of things, be such a thing as an inseparable accident. For if an attribute were found to belong invariably to all the members of a cla.s.s, we should suspect that there was some causal connection between it and the attributes which const.i.tute the definition, that is, we should suspect the attribute in question to be essential and not accidental. Nevertheless the term 'inseparable accident' may be retained as a cloak for our ignorance, whenever it is found that an attribute does, as a matter of fact, belong to all the members of a cla.s.s, without there being any apparent reason why it should do so. It has been observed that animals which have horns chew the cud. As no one can adduce any reason why animals that have horns should chew the cud any more than animals which have not, we may call the fact of chewing the cud an inseparable accident of horned animals.

-- 321. The distinction between separable and inseparable accidents is sometimes extended from cla.s.ses to individuals.

An inseparable accident of an individual is one which belongs to him at all times. A separable accident of an individual is one which belongs to him at one time and not at another.

-- 322. It is an inseparable accident of an individual that he was born at a certain place and on a certain date. It is a separable accident of an individual that he resides at a certain place and is of a certain age.

-- 323. There are some remarks which it may be well to make about the above five terms before we pa.s.s on to investigate the principle upon which the division is based.

-- 324. In the first place, it must of course be borne in mind that genus and species are relative terms. No cla.s.s in itself can be either a genus or a species; it only becomes so in reference to some other cla.s.s, as standing to it in the relation of containing or contained.

-- 325. Again, the distinction between genus and difference on the one hand and property on the other is wholly relative to an a.s.sumed definition. When we say 'Man is an animal,' 'Man is rational,' 'Man is progressive,' there is nothing in the nature of these statements themselves to tell us that the predicate is genus, difference, or property respectively. It is only by a tacit reference to the accepted definition of man that this becomes evident to us, Similarly, we cannot know beforehand that the fact of a triangle having three sides is its difference, and the fact of its having three angles a property. It is only when we a.s.sume the definition of a triangle as a three-sided figure that the fact of its having three angles sinks into a property. Had we chosen to define it, in accordance with its etymological meaning, as a figure with three angles, its three-sidedness would then have been a mere property, instead of being the difference; for these two attributes are so connected together that, whichever is postulated, the other will necessarily follow.

-- 326. Lastly, it must be noticed that we have not really defined the term 'accident,' not having stated what it is, but only what it is not. It has in fact been reserved as a residual head to cover any attribute which is neither a difference nor a property.

-- 327. If the five heads of predicables above given were offered to us as an exhaustive cla.s.sification of the possible relations in which the predicate can stand to the subject in a proposition, the first thing that would strike us is that they do not cover the case in which the predicate is a singular term. In such a proposition as 'This man is John,' we have neither a predication of genus or species nor of attribute: but merely the identification of one term with another, as applying to the same object. Such criticism as this, however, would be entirely erroneous, since no singular term was regarded as a predicate. A predicable was another name for a universal, the common term being called a predicable in one relation and a universal in another-a predicable, extensively, in so far as it was applicable to several different things, a universal, intensively, in so far as the attributes indicated were implied in several other notions, as the attributes indicated by 'animal' are implied in 'horse,' 'sheep,'

'goat,' &c.

-- 328. It would be less irrelevant to point out how the cla.s.sification breaks down in relation to the singular term as subject. When, for instance, we say 'Socrates is an animal,' 'Socrates is a man,' there is nothing in the proposition to show us whether the predicate is a genus or a species: for we have not here the relation of cla.s.s to cla.s.s, which gives us genus or species according to their relative extension, but the relation of a cla.s.s to an individual.

-- 329. Again, when we say

(1) Some animals are men,

(2) Some men are black,

what is there to tell us that the predicate is to be regarded in the one case as a species and in the other as an accident of the subject?

Nothing plainly but the a.s.sumption of a definition already known.

-- 330. But if this a.s.sumption be granted, the cla.s.sification seems to admit of a more or less complete defense by logic.

For, given any subject, we can predicate of it either a cla.s.s or an attribute.

When the predicate is a cla.s.s, the term predicated is called a Genus, if the subject itself be a cla.s.s, or a Species, if it be an individual.

When, on the other hand, the predicate is an attribute, the attribute predicated may be either the very attribute which distinguishes the subject from other members of the same cla.s.s, in which case it is called the Difference, or it may be some attribute connected with the definition, i.e. Property, or not connected with it, i.e. Accident.

-- 331. These results may be exhibited in the following scheme--

Predicate ________________|_________________ | | Cla.s.s Attribute ______|_______ __________|________ | | | | (Subject a (Subject a (The (Not the common singular distinguishing distinguishing term) term) Attribute) attribute) Genus Species Difference |___________________ | | (Connected (Not connected with the with the definition) definition) Property Accident

-- 332. The distinction which underlies this division between predicating a cla.s.s and predicating an attribute (in quid or in quale) is a perfectly intelligible one, corresponding as it does to the grammatical distinction between the predicate being a noun substantive or a noun adjective. Nevertheless it is a somewhat arbitrary one, since, even when the predicate is a cla.s.s-name, what we are concerned to convey to the mind, is the fact that the subject possesses the attributes which are connoted by that cla.s.s-name. We have not here the difference between extensive and intensive predication, since, as we have already seen (-- 264), that is not a difference between one proposition and another, but a distinction in our mode of interpreting any and every proposition. Whatever proposition we like to take may be read either in extension or in intension, according as we fix our minds on the fact of inclusion in a cla.s.s or the fact of the possession of attributes.

-- 333. It will be seen that the term 'species,' as it appears in the scheme, has a wholly different meaning from the current acceptation in which it was defined above. Species, in its now accepted meaning, signifies the relation of a smaller cla.s.s to a larger one: as it was originally intended in the heads of predicables it signifies a cla.s.s in reference to individuals.

-- 334. Another point which requires to be noticed with regard to this five-fold list of heads of predicables, if its object be to cla.s.sify the relations of a predicate to a subject, is that it takes no account of those forms of predication in which cla.s.s and attribute are combined. Under which of the five heads would the predicates in the following propositions fall?

(1) Man is a rational animal.

(2) Man is a featherless biped.

In the one case we have a combination of genus and difference; in the other we have a genus combined with an accident.

-- 335. The list of heads of predicables which we have been discussing is not derived from Aristotle, but from the 'Introduction' of Porphyry, a Greek commentator who lived more than six centuries later.

_Aristotle's Heads of Predicables_.

-- 336. Aristotle himself, by adopting a different basis of division, has allowed room in his cla.s.sification for the mixed forms of predication above alluded to. His list contains only four heads, namely,

Genus ([Greek: genos])

Definition ([Greek: rismos])

Proprium ([Greek: idion])

Accident ([Greek: sumbebekos])

-- 337. Genus here is not distinguished from difference. Whether we say 'Man is an animal' or 'Man is rational,' we are equally understood to be predicating a genus.

-- 338. There is no account taken of species, which, when predicated, resolves itself either into genus or accident. When predicated of an individual, it is regarded as a genus, e.g. 'Socrates is a man'; when predicated of a cla.s.s, it is regarded as an accident, e.g. 'Some animals are men.'

-- 339. Aristotle's cla.s.sification may easily be seen to be exhaustive. For every predicate must either be coextensive with its subject or not, i.e. predicable of the same things. And if the two terms coincide in extension, the predicate must either coincide also in intension with the subject or not.

A predicate which coincides both in extension and intension with its subject is exactly what is meant by a definition. One which coincides in extension without coinciding in intension, that is, which applies to the same things without expressing the whole meaning, of the subject, is what is known as a Proprium or Peculiar Property.

If, on the other hand, the two terms are not co-extensive, the predicate must either partially coincide in intension with the subject or not. [Footnote: The case could not arise of a predicate which was entirely coincided in intension with a subject with which it was not co-extensive. For, if the extension of the predicate were greater than that of the subject, its intension would be less, and if less, greater, in accordance with the law of inverse variation of the two quant.i.ties (-- 166).] This is equivalent to saying that it must either state part of the definition of the subject or not. Now the definition is made up of genus and difference, either of which may form the predicate: but as the two are indistinguishable in relation to a single subject, they are lumped together for the present purpose under the one head, genus. When the predicate, not being co-extensive, is not even partially co-intensive with its subject, it is called an Accident.

-- 340. Proprium, it will be seen, differs from property. A proprium is an attribute which is possessed by all the members of a cla.s.s, and by them alone, e.g. 'Men are the only religious animals.'

-- 341. Under the head of definition must be included all propositions in which the predicate is a mere synonym of the subject, e.g. 'Naso is Ovid,' 'A Hebrew is a Jew,' 'The skipper is the captain.' In such propositions the predicate coincides in extension with the subject, and may be considered to coincide in intension where the intension of both subject and predicate is at zero, as in the case of two proper names.

-- 342. Designations and descriptions will fall under the head of 'proprium' or peculiar property, e.g. 'Lord Salisbury is the present prime minister of England,' 'Man is a mammal with hands and without hair.' For here, while the terms are coincident in extension, they are far from being so in intension.

-- 343. The term 'genus' must be understood to include not only genus in the accepted sense, but difference and generic property as well.

-- 344. These results may be exhibited in the following scheme--

Predicate ___________________|______________ | | Coextensive with not the subject coextensive ________|_________ _____|________ | | | | Co-intensive not partially not at all with the subject cointensive cointensive [Greek: sumbubekos]

[Greek: rismos] [Greek: idion] [Greek: genos] Accident ______|_____ ______|_____________ |________________ | | | | | | | | Defini- Synonym Designa- Descrip- Peculiar Genus Differ- Generic tion tion tion Property ence Property

-- 345. Thus Aristotle's four heads of predicables may be split up, if we please, into nine--

Please click Like and leave more comments to support and keep us alive.

RECENTLY UPDATED MANGA

Deductive Logic Part 12 summary

You're reading Deductive Logic. This manga has been translated by Updating. Author(s): St. George William Joseph Stock. Already has 760 views.

It's great if you read and follow any novel on our website. We promise you that we'll bring you the latest, hottest novel everyday and FREE.

NovelOnlineFull.com is a most smartest website for reading manga online, it can automatic resize images to fit your pc screen, even on your mobile. Experience now by using your smartphone and access to NovelOnlineFull.com